Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology
David Graeber (2004)
Most academics seem to have only the
vaguest idea what anarchism is even about; or dismiss
it with the crudest stereotypes. (“Anarchist organization!
But isn’t that a contradiction in terms?”) In the
United States there are thousands of academic
Marxists of one sort or another, but hardly a dozen
scholars willing openly to call themselves anarchists. (2)
But it also makes it easier to understand why there are so
few anarchists in the academy. It’s not just that anarchism
does not tend to have much use for high theory.
It’s that it is primarily concerned with forms of practice; it insists, before anything else, that one’s means
must be consonant with one’s ends; one cannot create
freedom through authoritarian means; in fact, as much
as possible, one must oneself, in one’s relations with
one’s friends and allies, embody the society one wishes
to create. This does not square very well with operating
within the university, perhaps the only Western
institution other than the Catholic Church and British
monarchy that has survived in much the same form
from the Middle Ages, doing intellectual battle at
conferences in expensive hotels, and trying to pretend
all this somehow furthers revolution. At the very least,
one would imagine being an openly anarchist
professor would mean challenging the way universities
are run—and I don’t mean by demanding an anarchist
studies department, either—and that, of course, is
going to get one in far more trouble than anything
one could ever write. (6-7)
against policy (a tiny manifesto):
The notion of “policy” presumes a state or
governing apparatus which imposes its will on
others. “Policy” is the negation of politics; policy is
by definition something concocted by some form of
elite, which presumes it knows better than others
how their affairs are to be conducted. By participating
in policy debates the very best one can
achieve is to limit the damage, since the very
premise is inimical to the idea of people managing
their own affairs. (9)
It’s not so much that anthropologists embraced anarchism,
or even, were consciously espousing anarchist
ideas; it’s more that they moved in the same circles,
their ideas tended to bounce off one another, that
there was something about anthropological thought in
particular—its keen awareness of the very range of
human possibilities—that gave it an affinity to anarchism
from the very beginning. (13)
Before Mauss, the universal assumption had
been that economies without money or markets had
operated by means of “barter”; they were trying to
engage in market behavior (acquire useful goods and
services at the least cost to themselves, get rich if
possible...), they just hadn’t yet developed very
sophisticated ways of going about it. Mauss demonstrated
that in fact, such economies were really “gift
economies.” They were not based on calculation, but
on a refusal to calculate; they were rooted in an
ethical system which consciously rejected most of
what we would consider the basic principles of
economics. It was not that they had not yet learned to
seek profit through the most efficient means. They
would have found the very premise that the point of
an economic transaction—at least, one with someone
who was not your enemy—was to seek the greatest
profit deeply offensive.
It is significant that the one (of the few)
overtly anarchist anthropologists of recent memory,
another Frenchman, Pierre Clastres, became famous
for making a similar argument on the political level.
He insisted political anthropologists had still not
completely gotten over the old evolutionist perspectives
that saw the state primarily as a more sophisticated
form of organization than what had come
before; stateless peoples, such as the Amazonian societies
Clastres studied, were tacitly assumed not to have
attained the level of say, the Aztecs or the Inca. But
what if, he proposed, Amazonians were not entirely
unaware of what the elementary forms of state power
might be like—what it would mean to allow some men
to give everyone else orders which could not be questioned,
since they were backed up by the threat of
force—and were for that very reason determined to
ensure such things never came about? What if they
considered the fundamental premises of our political
science morally objectionable?
The parallels between the two arguments are
actually quite striking. In gift economies there are,
often, venues for enterprising individuals: But everything
is arranged in such a way they could never be
used as a platform for creating permanent inequalities
of wealth, since self-aggrandizing types all end up
competing to see who can give the most away. In
Amazonian (or North American) societies, the institution
of the chief played the same role on a political
level: the position was so demanding, and so little
rewarding, so hedged about by safeguards, that there
was no way for power-hungry individuals to do much
with it. Amazonians might not have literally whacked
off the ruler’s head every few years, but it’s not an
entirely inappropriate metaphor.
By these lights these were all, in a very real
sense, anarchist societies. (21-3)
The most common criticism of Clastres is to ask how
his Amazonians could really be organizing their societies
against the emergence of something they have
never actually experienced. A naive question, but it
points to something equally naive in Clastres’ own
approach. Clastres manages to talk blithely about the
uncompromised egalitarianism of the very same
Amazonian societies, for instance, famous for their
use of gang rape as a weapon to terrorize women
who transgress proper gender roles. It’s a blind spot
so glaring one has to wonder how he could possibly
miss out on it; especially considering it provides an
answer to just that question. Perhaps Amazonian men
understand what arbitrary, unquestionable power,
backed by force, would be like because they themselves
wield that sort of power over their wives and
daughters. Perhaps for that very reason they would
not like to see structures capable of inflicting it on
them.
It’s worth pointing out because Clastres is, in
many ways, a naive romantic. Fom another perspective,
though, there’s no mystery here at all. After all,
we are talking about the fact that most Amazonians
don’t want to give others the power to threaten them
with physical injury if they don’t do as they are told.
Maybe we should better be asking what it says about ourselves that we feel this attitude needs any sort of
explanation. (23-4)
I suspect all this turbulence stems from the
very nature of the human condition. There would
appear to be no society which does not see human life
as fundamentally a problem. However much they
might differ on what they deem the problem to be, at
the very least, the existence of work, sex, and reproduction
are seen as fraught with all sorts of quandaries;
human desires are always fickle; and then
there’s the fact that we’re all going to die. So there’s a
lot to be troubled by. None of these dilemmas are
going to vanish if we eliminate structural inequalities
(much though I think this would radically improve
things in just about every other way). Indeed, the
fantasy that it might, that the human condition,
desire, mortality, can all be somehow resolved seems
to be an especially dangerous one, an image of utopia
which always seems to lurk somewhere behind the
pretentions of Power and the state. (31)
The dice are loaded. You can’t win. Because
when the skeptic says “society,” what he really means
is “state,” even “nation-state.” Since no one is going to
produce an example of an anarchist state—that would
be a contradiction in terms—what we’re really being
asked for is an example of a modern nation-state with
the government somehow plucked away: a situation in
which the government of Canada, to take a random
example, has been overthrown, or for some reason
abolished itself, and no new one has taken its place but
instead all former Canadian citizens begin to organize
themselves into libertarian collectives. Obviously this
would never be allowed to happen. In the past, whenever
it even looked like it might—here, the Paris
commune and Spanish civil war are excellent examples—
the politicians running pretty much every state
in the vicinity have been willing to put their differences
on hold until those trying to bring such a situation
about had been rounded up and shot. (39)
If there is one logical error underlying all this,
it rests on imagining that social or even technological
change takes the same form of what Thomas
Kuhn has called “the structure of scientific revolutions.”
Kuhn is referring to events like the shift
from a Newtonian to Einsteinian universe:
suddenly there is an intellectual breakthrough and
afterwards, the universe is different. Applied to
anything other than scientific revolutions, it
implies that the world really was equivalent to our
knowledge of it, and the moment we change the
principles on which our knowledge is based, reality
changes too. This is just the sort of basic intellectual
mistake developmental psychologists say we’re
supposed to get over in early childhood, but it
seems few of us really do.(43)
A revolution on a world scale
will take a very long time. But it is also possible to
recognize that it is already starting to happen. The
easiest way to get our minds around it is to stop
thinking about revolution as a thing—“the” revolution,
the great cataclysmic break—and instead
ask “what is revolutionary action?” We could then
suggest: revolutionary action is any collective
action which rejects, and therefore confronts, some
form of power or domination and in doing so,
reconstitutes social relations—even within the
collectivity—in that light. Revolutionary action
does not necessarily have to aim to topple governments.
Attempts to create autonomous communities
in the face of power (using Castoriadis’ definition
here: ones that constitute themselves, collectively
make their own rules or principles of operation,
and continually reexamine them), would, for
instance, be almost by definition revolutionary
acts. And history shows us that the continual accumulation
of such acts can change (almost) everything. (45)
a thought experiment, or, blowing up walls
What I am proposing, essentially, is that we engage in
a kind of thought experiment. What if, as a recent title
put it, “we have never been modern”? What if there
never was any fundamental break, and therefore, we
are not living in a fundamentally different moral,
social, or political universe than the Piaroa or Tiv or
rural Malagasy?
There are a million different ways to define
“modernity.” According to some it mainly has to do
with science and technology, for others it’s a matter of
individualism; others, capitalism, or bureaucratic rationality,
or alienation, or an ideal of freedom of one sort
or another. However they define it, almost everyone
agrees that at somewhere in the sixteenth, or seventeenth,
or eighteenth centuries, a Great
Transformation occurred, that it occurred in Western
Europe and its settler colonies, and that because of it,
we became “modern.” And that once we did, we
became a fundamentally different sort of creature than
anything that had come before.
But what if we kicked this whole apparatus
away? What if we blew up the wall? What if we
accepted that the people who Columbus or Vasco da
Gama “discovered” on their expeditions were just us?
Or certainly, just as much “us” as Columbus and Vasco
da Gama ever were?
I’m not arguing that nothing important has
changed over the last five hundred years, any more
than I’m arguing that cultural differences are unimportant. In one sense everyone, every community,
every individual for that matter, lives in their own
unique universe. By “blowing up walls,” I mean most
of all, blowing up the arrogant, unreflecting assumptions
which tell us we have nothing in common with
98% of people who ever lived, so we don’t really have
to think about them. Since, after all, if you assume the
fundamental break, the only theoretical question you
can ask is some variation on “what makes us so
special?” Once we get rid of those assumptions, decide
to at least entertain the notion we aren’t quite so
special as we might like to think, we can also begin to
think about what really has changed and what hasn’t. (46-7)
But what we see in the more recent ethnographic
record is endless variety. There were huntergatherer
societies with nobles and slaves, there are
agrarian societies that are fiercely egalitarian. Even in
Clastres’ favored stomping grounds in Amazonia, one
finds some groups who can justly be described as anarchists,
like the Piaroa, living alongside others (say, the
warlike Sherente) who are clearly anything but. And
“societies” are constantly reforming, skipping back
and forth between what we think of as different evolutionary
stages.
I do not think we’re losing much if we admit
that humans never really lived in the garden of Eden.
Knocking the walls down can allow us to see this
history as a resource to us in much more interesting
ways. (54)
The Vezo lived alongside the Sakalava
monarchies but like the Tsimihety, they managed to
remain independent of them because, as legend has
it, whenever they learned royal representatives were
on the way to visit them, they would all get in their
canoes and wait offshore until they went away.
Those fishing villages that did succumb became
Sakalava, not Vezo.(58)
In many other parts of Madagascar as well, it often
seems that no one really takes on their full authority
until they are dead. So perhaps the Sakalava case is
not that extraordinary. But it reveals one very
common way of avoiding the direct effects of power:
if one cannot simply step out of its path, like the Vezo
or Tsimihety, one can, as it were, try to fossilize it. In
the Sakalava case the ossification of the state is quite
literal: the kings who are still worshipped take the
physical form of royal relics, they are literally teeth
and bones. But this approach is probably far more
commonplace than we would be given to suspect. (59)
The theory of exodus proposes that the most
effective way of opposing capitalism and the liberal
state is not through direct confrontation but by means
of what Paolo Virno has called “engaged withdrawal,”
mass defection by those wishing to create new forms
of community. One need only glance at the historical
record to confirm that most successful forms of
popular resistance have taken precisely this form.
They have not involved challenging power head on
(this usually leads to being slaughtered, or if not,
turning into some—often even uglier—variant of the
very thing one first challenged) but from one or
another strategy of slipping away from its grasp, from
flight, desertion, the founding of new communities. (60-1)
Which leads to the question of how to neutralize the
state apparatus itself, in the absence of a politics of
direct confrontation. No doubt some states and corporate
elites will collapse of their own dead weight; a few
already have; but it’s hard to imagine a scenario in
which they all will. Here, the Sakalava and BaKongo
might be able to provide us some useful suggestions.
What cannot be destroyed can, nonetheless, be
diverted, frozen, transformed, and gradually deprived
of its substance—which in the case of states, is ultimately
their capacity to inspire terror. What would
this mean under contemporary conditions? It’s not
entirely clear. Perhaps existing state apparati will gradually
be reduced to window-dressing as the substance
is pulled out of them from above and below: i.e., both
from the growth of international institutions, and
from devolution to local and regional forms of selfgovernance.
Perhaps government by media spectacle
will devolve into spectacle pure and simple (somewhat
along the lines of what Paul Lafargue, Marx’s West
Indian son-in-law and author of The Right to Be Lazy,
implied when he suggested that after the revolution,
politicians would still be able to fulfill a useful social
function in the entertainment industry). More likely it
will happen in ways we cannot even anticipate. But no
doubt there are ways in which it is happening already.
As Neoliberal states move towards new forms of
feudalism, concentrating their guns increasingly
around gated communities, insurrectionary spaces
open up that we don’t even know about. The Merina
rice farmers described in the last section understand
what many would-be revolutionaries do not: that there
are times when the stupidest thing one could possibly
do is raise a red or black flag and issue defiant declarations.
Sometimes the sensible thing is just to pretend
nothing has changed, allow official state representatives
to keep their dignity, even show up at their
offices and fill out a form now and then, but otherwise,
ignore them. (62-3)
Tenets of a Non-existent Science
Let me outline a few of the areas of theory an anarchist
anthropology might wish to explore:
1) A THEORY OF THE STATE
States have a peculiar dual character. They are at
the same time forms of institutionalized raiding or
extortion, and utopian projects. The first certainly
reflects the way states are actually experienced, by
any communities that retain some degree of
autonomy; the second however is how they tend to
appear in the written record.
In one sense states are the “imaginary totality”
par excellence, and much of the confusion entailed
in theories of the state historically lies in an
inability or unwillingness to recognize this. For the
most part, states were ideas, ways of imagining
social order as something one could get a grip on,
models of control. This is why the first known
works of social theory, whether from Persia, or
China, or ancient Greece, were always framed as
theories of statecraft. This has had two disastrous
effects. One is to give utopianism a bad name. (The
word “utopia” first calls to mind the image of an
ideal city, usually, with perfect geometry—the
image seems to harken back originally to the royal
military camp: a geometrical space which is entirely
the emanation of a single, individual will, a fantasy
of total control.) All this has had dire political
consequences, to say the least. The second is that
we tend to assume that states, and social order,
even societies, largely correspond. In other words,
we have a tendency to take the most grandiose,
even paranoid, claims of world-rulers seriously,
assuming that whatever cosmological projects they
claimed to be pursuing actually did correspond, at
least roughly, to something on the ground.
Whereas it is likely that in many such cases, these
claims ordinarily only applied fully within a few
dozen yards of the monarch in any direction, and
most subjects were much more likely to see ruling
elites, on a day-to-day basis, as something much
along the lines of predatory raiders.
An adequate theory of states would then have
to begin by distinguishing in each case between the
relevant ideal of rulership (which can be almost
anything, a need to enforce military style discipline,
the ability to provide perfect theatrical representation
of gracious living which will inspire others, the
need to provide the gods with endless human
hearts to fend off the apocalypse...), and the
mechanics of rule, without assuming that there is
necessarily all that much correspondence between
them. (There might be. But this has to be empirically
established.) For example: much of the
mythology of “the West” goes back to Herodotus’
description of an epochal clash between the Persian
Empire, based on an ideal of obedience and
absolute power, and the Greek cities of Athens and
Sparta, based on ideals of civic autonomy, freedom
and equality. It’s not that these ideas—especially
their vivid representations in poets like Aeschylus
or historians like Herodotus—are not important.
One could not possibly understand Western history
without them. But their very importance and vividness
long blinded historians to what is becoming
the increasingly clear reality: that whatever its
ideals, the Achmaenid Empire was a pretty light
touch when it came to the day-to-day control of its
subjects’ lives, particularly in comparison with the
degree of control exercised by Athenians over their
slaves or Spartans over the overwhelming majority
of the Laconian population, who were helots.
Whatever the ideals, the reality, for most people
involved, was much the other way around.
One of the most striking discoveries of evolutionary
anthropology has been that it is perfectly
possible to have kings and nobles and all the exterior
trappings of monarchy without having a state
in the mechanical sense at all. One should think
this might be of some interest to all those political
philosophers who spill so much ink arguing about
theories of “sovereignty”—since it suggests that
most sovereigns were not heads of state and that
their favorite technical term actually is built on a
near-impossible ideal, in which royal power actually
does manage to translate its cosmological pretensions
into genuine bureaucratic control of a given
territorial population. (Something like this started
happening in Western Europe in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries, but almost as soon as it did,
the sovereign’s personal power was replaced by a
fictive person called “the people,” allowing the
bureaucracy to take over almost entirely.) But so far
as I’m aware, political philosophers have as yet had
nothing to say on the subject. I suspect this is
largely due to an extremely poor choice of terms.
Evolutionary anthropologists refer to kingdoms
which lack full-fledged coercive bureaucracies as
“chiefdoms,” a term which evokes images more of
Geronimo or Sitting Bull than Solomon, Louis the
Pious, or the Yellow Emperor. And of course the
evolutionist framework itself ensures that such
structures are seen as something which immediately
precedes the emergence of the state, not an alternative
form, or even something a state can turn into.
To clarify all this would be a major historical
project. (65-8)
Athens’ police force consisted of
Scythian archers imported from what’s now Russia
or Ukraine, and something of their legal standing
might be gleaned from the fact that, by Athenian
law, a slave’s testimony was not admissible as
evidence in court unless it was obtained under
torture. (69)
With the
current crisis of the nation-state and rapid increase
in international institutions which are not exactly
states, but in many ways just as obnoxious, juxtaposed
against attempts to create international institutions
which do many of the same things as states
but would be considerably less obnoxious, the lack
of such a body of theory is becoming a genuine
crisis. (70)
At the very least we need a proper theory of the
history of wage labor, and relations like it. Since
after all, it is in performing wage labor, not in
buying and selling, that most humans now waste
away most of their waking hours and it is that
which makes them miserable. (71)
Academics love Michel Foucault’s argument that
identifies knowledge and power, and insists that
brute force is no longer a major factor in social
control. They love it because it flatters them: the
perfect formula for people who like to think of
themselves as political radicals even though all they
do is write essays likely to be read by a few dozen
other people in an institutional environment. Of
course, if any of these academics were to walk into
their university library to consult some volume of
Foucault without having remembered to bring a
valid ID, and decided to enter the stacks anyway,
they would soon discover that brute force is really
not so far away as they like to imagine—a man with
a big stick, trained in exactly how hard to hit
people with it, would rapidly appear to eject them.
In fact the threat of that man with the stick
permeates our world at every moment; most of us
have given up even thinking of crossing the innumerable
lines and barriers he creates, just so we
don’t have to remind ourselves of his existence. If
you see a hungry woman standing several yards
away from a huge pile of food—a daily occurrence
for most of us who live in cities—there is a reason
you can’t just take some and give it to her. A man
with a big stick will come and very likely hit you.
Anarchists, in contrast, have always delighted in
reminding us of him. Residents of the squatter
community of Christiana, Denmark, for example,
have a Christmastide ritual where they dress in
Santa suits, take toys from department stores and
distribute them to children on the street, partly just
so everyone can relish the images of the cops
beating down Santa and snatching the toys back
from crying children.
Such a theoretical emphasis opens the way to a
theory of the relation of power not with knowledge,
but with ignorance and stupidity. Because
violence, particularly structural violence, where all
the power is on one side, creates ignorance. If you
have the power to hit people over the head whenever
you want, you don’t have to trouble yourself
too much figuring out what they think is going on,
and therefore, generally speaking, you don’t. Hence
the sure-fire way to simplify social arrangements, to
ignore the incredibly complex play of perspectives,
passions, insights, desires, and mutual understandings
that human life is really made of, is to make a
rule and threaten to attack anyone who breaks it.
This is why violence has always been the favored
recourse of the stupid: it is the one form of
stupidity to which it is almost impossible to come
up with an intelligent response. It is also of course
the basis of the state.
Contrary to popular belief, bureaucracies do
not create stupidity. They are ways of managing
situations that are already inherently stupid because
they are, ultimately, based on the arbitrariness of
force.
Ultimately this should lead to a theory of the
relation of violence and the imagination. Why is it
that the folks on the bottom (the victims of structural
violence) are always imagining what it must be
like for the folks on top (the beneficiaries of structural
violence), but it almost never occurs to the
folks on top to wonder what it might be like to be
on the bottom? Human beings being the sympathetic
creatures that they are this tends to become
one of the main bastions of any system of
inequality—the downtrodden actually care about
their oppressors, at least, far more than their
oppressors care about them—but this seems itself
to be an effect of structural violence. (71-3)
SUFFERING AND PLEASURE: ON THE
PRIVATIZATION OF DESIRE
It is common wisdom among anarchists, autonomists,
Situationists, and other new revolutionaries
that the old breed of grim, determined, self-sacrificing
revolutionary, who sees the world only in
terms of suffering will ultimately only produce
more suffering himself. Certainly that’s what has
tended to happen in the past. Hence the emphasis
on pleasure, carnival, on creating “temporary
autonomous zones” where one can live as if one is
already free. (74)
We could start with a kind of sociology of
micro-utopias, the counterpart of a parallel
typology of forms of alienation, alienated and nonalienated
forms of action... The moment we stop
insisting on viewing all forms of action only by
their function in reproducing larger, total, forms of
inequality of power, we will also be able to see that
anarchist social relations and non-alienated forms
of action are all around us. And this is critical
because it already shows that anarchism is, already,
and has always been, one of the main bases for
human interaction. We self-organize and engage in
mutual aid all the time. We always have. (76)
Q: How many voters does it take to change a
light bulb?
A: None. Because voters can’t change anything.(77)
As I’ve mentioned, the “anti-globalization movement”
is increasingly anarchist in inspiration. In the long
run the anarchist position on globalization is obvious:
the effacement of nation-states will mean the elimination
of national borders. This is genuine globalization.
Anything else is just a sham. (77)
The
moment the average resident of Tanzania, or Laos,
was no longer forbidden to relocate to Minneapolis or
Rotterdam, the government of every rich and
powerful country in the world would certainly decide
nothing was more important than finding a way to
make sure people in Tanzania and Laos preferred to
stay there. Do you really think they couldn’t come up
with something?
The point is that despite the endless rhetoric
about “complex, subtle, intractable issues” (justifying
decades of expensive research by the rich and their
well-paid flunkies), the anarchist program would
probably have resolved most of them in five or six
years. But, you will say, these demands are entirely
unrealistic! True enough. But why are they unrealistic?
Mainly, because those rich guys meeting in the
Waldorf would never stand for any of it. This is why
we say they are themselves the problem. (78-9)
So the
Wobblies have reappeared, with what was to be the
next step in their program, even back in the ‘20s: the
16-hour week. (“4-day week, 4-hour day.”) Again, on
the face of it, this seems completely unrealistic, even
insane. But has anyone carried out a feasibility study?
After all, it has been repeatedly demonstrated that a
considerable chunk of the hours worked in America
are only actually necessary to compensate for problems
created by the fact that Americans work too
much. (Consider here such jobs as all-night pizza
deliveryman or dog-washer, or those women who run
nighttime day care centers for the children of women
who have to work nights providing child care for
businesswomen...not to mention the endless hours
spent by specialists cleaning up the emotional and
physical damage caused by overwork, the injuries,
suicides, divorces, murderous rampages, producing
the drugs to pacify the children...)
So what jobs are really necessary?
Well, for starters, there are lots of jobs whose
disappearance, almost everyone would agree, would
be a net gain for humanity. Consider here telemarketers,
stretch-SUV manufacturers, or for that matter,
corporate lawyers. We could also eliminate the entire
advertising and PR industries, fire all politicians and
their staffs, eliminate anyone remotely connected with
an HMO, without even beginning to get near essential
social functions. The elimination of advertising
would also reduce the production, shipping, and
selling of unnecessary products, since those items
people actually do want or need, they will still figure
out a way to find out about. The elimination of
radical inequalities would mean we would no longer
require the services of most of the millions currently
employed as doormen, private security forces, prison
guards, or SWAT teams—not to mention the military.
Beyond that, we’d have to do research. Financiers,
insurers, and investment bankers are all essentially
parasitic beings, but there might be some useful functions
in these sectors that could not simply be
replaced with software. All in all we might discover
that if we identified the work that really did need to
be done to maintain a comfortable and ecologically
sustainable standard of living, and redistribute the
hours, it may turn out that the Wobbly platform is
perfectly realistic. Especially if we bear in mind that
it’s not like anyone would be forced to stop working
after four hours if they didn’t feel like it. A lot of
people do enjoy their jobs, certainly more than they
would lounging around doing nothing all day (that’s
why in prisons, when they want to punish inmates,
they take away their right to work), and if one has
eliminated the endless indignities and sadomasochistic
games that inevitably follow from top-down organization,
one would expect a lot more would. It might
even turn out that no one will have to work more
than they particularly want to. (80-1)
This might give the reader a chance to have a glance
at what anarchist, and anarchist-inspired, organizing is
actually like—some of the contours of the new world
now being built in the shell of the old—and to show
what the historical-ethnographic perspective I’ve been
trying to develop here, our non-existent science,
might be able to contribute to it.
The first cycle of the new global uprising—
what the press still insists on referring to, increasingly
ridiculously, as “the anti-globalization movement”—
began with the autonomous municipalities of Chiapas
and came to a head with the asambleas barreales of
Buenos Aires, and cities throughout Argentina. There
is hardly room here to tell the whole story: beginning
with the Zapatistas’ rejection of the idea of seizing
power and their attempt instead to create a model of
democratic self-organization to inspire the rest of
Mexico; their initiation of an international network
(People’s Global Action, or PGA) which then put out
the calls for days of action against the WTO (in
Seattle), IMF (in Washington, Prague...) and so on;
and finally, the collapse of the Argentine economy, and
the overwhelming popular uprising which, again,
rejected the very idea that one could find a solution by
replacing one set of politicians with another. The
slogan of the Argentine movement was, from the start,
que se vayan todas—get rid of the lot of them. Instead
of a new government they created a vast network of
alternative institutions, starting with popular assemblies
to govern each urban neighborhood (the only
limitation on participation is that one cannot be
employed by a political party), hundreds of occupied,
worker-managed factories, a complex system of
“barter” and newfangled alternative currency system
to keep them in operation—in short, an endless variation
on the theme of direct democracy.
All of this has happened completely below the
radar screen of the corporate media, which also missed
the point of the great mobilizations. The organization
of these actions was meant to be a living illustration of
what a truly democratic world might be like, from the
festive puppets to the careful organization of affinity
groups and spokescouncils, all operating without a
leadership structure, always based on principles of
consensus-based direct democracy. It was the kind of
organization which most people would have, had they
simply heard it proposed, written off as a pipe-dream;
but it worked, and so effectively that the police departments
of city after city were completely flummoxed
with how to deal with them. Of course, this also had
something to do with the unprecedented tactics
(hundreds of activists in fairy suits tickling police with
feather dusters, or padded with so many inflatable
inner tubes and rubber cushions they seemed to roll
along like the Michelin man over barricades, incapable
of damaging anyone else but also pretty much impervious
to police batons...), which completely confused
traditional categories of violence and nonviolence. (82-4)
In fact, as anthropologists are aware, just
about every known human community which has to
come to group decisions has employed some variation
of what I’m calling “consensus process”—every one,
that is, which is not in some way or another drawing
on the tradition of ancient Greece. Majoritarian
democracy, in the formal, Roberts Rules of Ordertype
sense rarely emerges of its own accord. It’s
curious that almost no one, anthropologists included,
ever seems to ask oneself why this should be. (86-7)
The real reason for the unwillingness of most
scholars to see a Sulawezi or Tallensi village council
as “democratic”—well, aside from simple racism,
the reluctance to admit anyone Westerners slaughtered
with such relative impunity were quite on the
level as Pericles—is that they do not vote. Now,
admittedly, this is an interesting fact. Why not? If
we accept the idea that a show of hands, or having
everyone who supports a proposition stand on one
side of the plaza and everyone against stand on the
other, are not really such incredibly sophisticated
ideas that they never would have occurred to
anyone until some ancient genius “invented” them,
then why are they so rarely employed? Again, we
seem to have an example of explicit rejection. Over
and over, across the world, from Australia to
Siberia, egalitarian communities have preferred
some variation on consensus process. Why?
The explanation I would propose is this: it is
much easier, in a face-to-face community, to figure
out what most members of that community want to
do, than to figure out how to convince those who do
not to go along with it. Consensus decision-making
is typical of societies where there would be no way
to compel a minority to agree with a majority decision—
either because there is no state with a
monopoly of coercive force, or because the state has
nothing to do with local decision-making. If there is
no way to compel those who find a majority decision
distasteful to go along with it, then the last thing one
would want to do is to hold a vote: a public contest
which someone will be seen to lose. Voting would be
the most likely means to guarantee humiliations,
resentments, hatreds, in the end, the destruction of
communities. What is seen as an elaborate and difficult
process of finding consensus is, in fact, a long
process of making sure no one walks away feeling
that their views have been totally ignored.
Majority democracy, we might say, can only
emerge when two factors coincide:
1. a feeling that people should have equal say in
making group decisions, and
2. a coercive apparatus capable of enforcing those
decisions.
For most of human history, it has been extremely
unusual to have both at the same time. Where egalitarian
societies exist, it is also usually considered
wrong to impose systematic coercion. Where a
machinery of coercion did exist, it did not even
occur to those wielding it that they were enforcing
any sort of popular will.
It is of obvious relevance that Ancient Greece
was one of the most competitive societies known
to history. It was a society that tended to make
everything into a public contest, from athletics to
philosophy or tragic drama or just about anything
else. So it might not seem entirely surprising that
they made political decision-making into a public
contest as well. Even more crucial though was the
fact that decisions were made by a populace in
arms. Aristotle, in his Politics, remarks that the
constitution of a Greek city-state will normally
depend on the chief arm of its military: if this is
cavalry, it will be an aristocracy, since horses are
expensive. If hoplite infantry, it will have an
oligarchy, as all could not afford the armor and
training. If its power was based in the navy or light
infantry, one could expect a democracy, as anyone
can row, or use a sling. In other words if a man is
armed, then one pretty much has to take his opinions
into account. One can see how this worked at
its starkest in Xenophon’s Anabasis, which tells the
story of an army of Greek mercenaries who
suddenly find themselves leaderless and lost in the
middle of Persia. They elect new officers, and then
hold a collective vote to decide what to do next. In
a case like this, even if the vote was 60/40,
everyone could see the balance of forces and what
would happen if things actually came to blows.
Every vote was, in a real sense, a conquest.
Roman legions could be similarly democratic;
this was the main reason they were never allowed
to enter the city of Rome. And when Machiavelli
revived the notion of a democratic republic at the
dawn of the “modern” era, he immediately
reverted to the notion of a populace in arms.
This in turn might help explain the term
“democracy” itself, which appears to have been
coined as something of a slur by its elitist opponents:
it literally means the “force” or even
“violence” of the people. Kratos, not archos. The
elitists who coined the term always considered
democracy not too far from simple rioting or mob
rule; though of course their solution was the
permanent conquest of the people by someone
else. And ironically, when they did manage to
suppress democracy for this reason, which was
usually, the result was that the only way the
general populace’s will was known was precisely
through rioting, a practice that became quite institutionalized
in, say, imperial Rome or eighteenth-century
England. (88-91)
I noted earlier that all social orders are in
some sense at war with themselves. Those unwilling to
establish an apparatus of violence for enforcing decisions
necessarily have to develop an apparatus for
creating and maintaining social consensus (at least in
that minimal sense of ensuring malcontents can still
feel they have freely chosen to go along with bad decisions);
as an apparent result, the internal war ends up
projected outwards into endless night battles and
forms of spectral violence. Majoritarian direct democracy
is constantly threatening to make those lines of
force explicit. For this reason it does tend to be rather
unstable: or more precisely, if it does last, it’s because
its institutional forms (the medieval city, New England
town council, for that matter gallup polls, referendums...)
are almost invariably ensconced within a
larger framework of governance in which ruling elites
use that very instability to justify their ultimate
monopoly of the means of violence. Finally, the threat
of this instability becomes an excuse for a form of
“democracy” so minimal that it comes down to
nothing more than insisting that ruling elites should
occasionally consult with “the public”—in carefully
staged contests, replete with rather meaningless jousts
and tournaments—to reestablish their right to go on
making their decisions for them.
It’s a trap. Bouncing back and forth between
the two ensures it will remain extremely unlikely that
one could ever imagine it would be possible for people
to manage their own lives, without the help of “representatives.”
It’s for this reason the new global movement
has begun by reinventing the very meaning of
democracy. To do so ultimately means, once again,
coming to terms with the fact that “we”—whether as
“the West” (whatever that means), as the “modern
world,” or anything else—are not really as special as
we like to think we are; that we’re not the only people
ever to have practiced democracy; that in fact, rather
than disseminating democracy around the world,
“Western” governments have been spending at least as
much time inserting themselves into the lives of
people who have been practicing democracy for thousands
of years, and in one way or another, telling them
to cut it out. (92-3)
The final question—one that I’ve admittedly been
rather avoiding up to now—is why anthropologists
haven’t, so far? I have already described why I think
academics, in general, have rarely felt much affinity
with anarchism. I’ve talked a little about the radical
inclinations in much early twentieth-century anthropology,
which often showed a very strong affinity with
anarchism, but that seemed to largely evaporate over
time. It’s all a little odd. Anthropologists are after all
the only group of scholars who know anything about
actually-existing stateless societies; many have actually
lived in corners of the world where states have ceased
to function or at least temporarily pulled up stakes and
left, and people are managing their own affairs
autonomously; if nothing else, they are keenly aware
that the most commonplace assumptions about what
would happen in the absence of a state (“but people
would just kill each other!”) are factually untrue. (95)
There’s more to it though. In many ways,
anthropology seems a discipline terrified of its own
potential. It is, for example, the only discipline in a
position to make generalizations about humanity as a
whole—since it is the only discipline that actually
takes all of humanity into account, and is familiar with
all the anomalous cases. (“All societies practice
marriage, you say? Well that depends on how you
define ‘marriage.’ Among the Nayar...”) Yet it
resolutely refuses to do so. (97)
Many years ago a French anthropologist
named Gerard Althabe wrote a book about
Madagascar called Oppression et Liberation dans
l’Imaginaire. It’s a catchy phrase. I think it might well
be applied to what ends up happening in a lot of
anthropological writing. For the most part, what we
call “identities” here, in what Paul Gilroy likes to call
the “over-developed world,” are forced on people. In
the United States, most are the products of ongoing
oppression and inequality: someone who is defined as
Black is not allowed to forget that during a single
moment of their existence; his or her own self-definition is of no significance to the banker who will deny
him credit, or the policeman who will arrest him for
being in the wrong neighborhood, or the doctor who,
in the case of a damaged limb, will be more likely to
recommend amputation. All attempts at individual or
collective self-fashioning or self-invention have to take
place entirely within those extremely violent sets of
constraints. (The only real way that could change
would be to transform the attitudes of those who have
the privilege of being defined as “White”—ultimately,
probably, by destroying the category of Whiteness
itself.) The fact is though that nobody has any idea
how most people in North America would chose to
define themselves if institutional racism were to actually
vanish—if everyone really were left free to define
themselves however they wished. Neither is there
much point in speculating about it. The question is
how to create a situation where we could find out.
This is what I mean by “liberation in the
imaginary.” To think about what it would take to live
in a world in which everyone really did have the
power to decide for themselves, individually and
collectively, what sort of communities they wished to
belong to and what sort of identities they wanted to
take on—that’s really difficult. To bring about such a
world would be almost unimaginably difficult. It
would require changing almost everything. It also
would meet with stubborn, and ultimately violent,
opposition from those who benefit the most from
existing arrangements. To instead write as if these
identities are already freely created—or largely so—is
easy, and it lets one entirely off the hook for the intricate and intractable problems of the degree to which
one’s own work is part of this very identity machine. (101-3)
This strategy has not been entirely ineffective.
Ten years later, the Zapatista Army of National
Liberation is still there, without having hardly had
to fire a shot, if only because they have been
willing, for the time being, to downplay the
“National” part in their name. All I want to emphasize
is exactly how patronizing—or, maybe let’s not
pull punches here, how completely racist—the
international reaction to the Zapatista rebellion has
really been. Because what the Zapatistas were
proposing to do was exactly to begin that difficult
work that, I pointed out, so much of the rhetoric
about “identity” effectively ignores: trying to work
out what forms of organization, what forms of
process and deliberation, would be required to
create a world in which people and communities
are actually free to determine for themselves what
sort of people and communities they wish to be.
And what were they told? Effectively, they were
informed that, since they were Maya, they could
not possibly have anything to say to the world
about the processes through which identity is
constructed; or about the nature of political possibilities.
As Mayas, the only possible political statement
they could make to non-Mayas would be
about their Maya identity itself. They could assert
the right to continue to be Mayan. They could
demand recognition as Mayan. But for a Maya to
say something to the world that was not simply a
comment on their own Maya-ness would be inconceivable.
And who was listening to what they really had
to say?
Largely, it seems, a collection of teenage anarchists
in Europe and North America, who soon began
besieging the summits of the very global elite to
whom anthropologists maintain such an uneasy,
uncomfortable, alliance.
But the anarchists were right. I think anthropologists
should make common cause with them. We
have tools at our fingertips that could be of enormous
importance for human freedom. Let’s start taking
some responsibility for it. (104-5)
|